A correspondent (code name emergence) sent me a letter asking an interesting question about epistemology…

Hey Dr. Carrier, I realize that this might be kind of off-topic, but I was talking about philosophy in the Thunderdome on Pharyngula, and you were recommended to me as the guy to go to for philosophy questions. I understand if you’re busy, but I wanted to ask a few questions about something that’s been bothering me. I’ve been thinking about a lot of famous epistemological dilemmas lately, like the regress argument, Descartes’s evil deceiver, or the problem of induction. There are a few other minor ones, but those are the main 3. In trying to understand them, I think that I’ve been able to figure out some solutions to some of them.

I want to talk about the infinite regress first. This argument seems to have several different facets, and I’ve noticed that it might bring up a few other ideas that not many people have touched on. There’s even a bit of overlap with the idea of the evil deceiver. For now, I just want to present my main solution to the issue, and ask a few questions about it.

This is my general argument:

  1. The foundation of the logical chain starts with my own thoughts and perceptions. Specifically, my experiences of them. This is where the issue sort of overlaps with the evil deceiver. Even if I’m just a brain in a tank, I’m still experiencing something. There are still images and sounds that I am experiencing, even if they don’t correspond to anything real. The reason that I know that I am experiencing them is purely because I am, in fact, directly experiencing them. I don’t infer that I am experiencing my own thoughts or perceptions from anything other than my experiences of them. This is also how I know that I exist. I have a subjective experience of existence.
  2. I know that abstract concepts like “existence”, “non-existence”, “location”, “quantity”, etc. exist because they are generalizations and idealizations that I use to describe what I perceive. For example, I have a concept of “existence” because I use that term to describe something that I perceive. If I perceive something to “be”, I call that “existence”. It doesn’t matter that what I’m perceiving could be an illusion. I still have the abstract concept inside of my mind.
  3. I know that the basic rules of logic (non-contradiction, identity, excluded middle, etc.) are true because of my understanding of the abstract concepts that they describe. For example, I know that “something is itself” is true because of what I understand the terms “something”, “is”, and “itself” to mean.

Now on to what I’m still iffy about:

  1. In my first point, I say that I justify my belief that I experience thoughts and perceptions through my experience of them. Is this circular reasoning?
  2. The second point that I make seems to rely on the idea that I can know that the abstract concept of something exists purely by experiencing a perception of that thing. For example, I can know that the abstract concept of a circle exists purely from experiencing a perception of a circular object, even if that perception is an illusion that doesn’t represent anything in objective reality. Are there any problems with this?
  3. Is there something wrong with the fact that this line of argument is so complicated? I feel like the fact that this idea is so long somehow disqualifies it from solving the regress argument. I also feel like all of the side-explanations might need to be justified as well.
  4. Am I overthinking this issue?

I’m sorry if this was too long, or anything else like that. I just really want to get some answers to these questions.

The short answer? No, no, no, and…drum roll…no.

For those who want to catch up to this point in the conversation, I tackle the regress problem in the context of my epistemology in Epistemological End Game. Relevant discussions of my epistemology (in application as well as construction) are in Sense and Goodness without God (Chs. II, III.6, III.9) and Proving History (Ch. 2; plus see the index, “gerrymandering (a theory)”).

My answer in more detail is, in reverse order:

  1. [i.e. 4] To do good philosophy, it’s not overthinking it to ask any question that you don’t already know the obvious answer to. A grounded epistemology in fact requires overthinking, so you can be sure it’s all been thought out. You don’t have to dwell on the overthought. But it’s good to have thought it through.
  2. [i.e. 3] The machine you are trying to explain (a consciousness-producing mind, ostensibly floating through a whole universe, attempting to produce knowledge of both) is (and indeed must necessarily be) vastly complex. So you should expect any explanation of how that mind mediates its access to itself and the outside world so as to construct perception and understanding will not likely be a simple one. If it were simple, that would be spooky. Remember, we are starting with the output of a machine (perception events). We are not starting with anything actually ontologically simple (like a photon or space-time). And we are trying to ascertain what connection those outputs (perception events) have to anything apart from them (an external world, which also includes the machine generating those outputs we are observing). Analogously, watching a movie, the flow of the images on a wall looks really simple (it’s just colored light, reforming effortlessly). But if you ask what is producing it, you should expect, and will discover, it’s a really complicated machine, combined with a really complicated causal history involving an even more complex social system (e.g. the Hollywood Industrial Complex).
  3. [i.e. 2] Abstractions are just names for sets of perception events with a common characteristic. So you are creating them in your concept-space, out of the raw undeniable data presented to you in your consciousness. They are therefore as undeniably certain as the perception events of which they are assembled. There really isn’t any problem explaining abstraction, which is just “information processing” the data of perception. Philosophers who think abstraction has to be “hyper-real” in some independent sense for commonalities to exist outside the mind are the ones off the rails. Once circles are capable of existing, nothing else needs to exist to explain why they have common features, or why we can assign a code word to designate those common features. See Defining Naturalism for my discussion of mathematical abstractions as an example. This also comes up at many points in my Critique of Reppert. And its application to rule out solipsistic and rule in physicalist explanations of our experiences is outlined in my Critique of Rea.
  4. [i.e. 1] If the existence of a perception event is literally undeniable, that means there is no logically possible way it can be false to say it exists (when experienced). That’s not a fallacy of circular argument. Because circular arguments only exist when something that needs proof remains unproven. But logically necessary truths are allowed to be circular because they are incapable of being false (unlike a fallacious circular argument, whose conclusion is capable of being false, that’s why it’s a fallacy). They can’t be false because by definition they are necessarily true. In fact, by definition, all tautologies are necessarily true. That’s actually a really handy feature of them, epistemically speaking. It just sucks that most of the things we want to know are not tautologies. But we start at those things on a foundation of tautologies: facts that are incapable of being false. Pointing out that the proposition “I am having x experience right now” is incapable of being false is not a circular argument. It’s just a tautological description of the data.

Since Sense and Goodness was published I have come to conclude that Bayesian epistemology is correct (The Gettier Problem, Two Bayesian Fallacies, etc.) and that is reflected in Proving History (especially in Chs. 4 and 6). This allows a potential solution to the problem of induction, especially when using Laplacean reasoning. The upshot is: regress ends with facts that cannot be false (raw uninterpreted present experience); what we can infer from those facts is probabilistically true by virtue of deductively certain logic (so induction does not require a circular presumption of the future resembling the past); because Cartesian demons are the only alternative hypothesis with a competitive consequent probability of producing the same evidence, yet Cartesian demons are necessarily vastly more complex than explanations lacking them, and therefore have vastly smaller prior probabilities (as I explain in Defining the Supernatural vs. Logical Positivism).

That Cartesian demons are vastly improbable is a fact deductively certain from the data undeniably present to us and therefore incapable of being false. The data, that is, is incapable of being false; the deduction could still be false, e.g. if we are making a mistake in the logic somewhere unbeknownst to us, but that is simply one more consideration of the probability of such a mistake entailed by the undeniable data. In other words, the data we have entails the probability that we are wrong about this is small.

An illustration of that is: a weakest Cartesian Demon is your friends pranking you (a somewhat more convoluted and thus more complex explanation of what you are experiencing than that you are just experiencing the true state of the world right now); a much stronger but still weak Cartesian Demon is The Truman Show (which is far more complicated in the system required to realize it); a far better Cartesian Demon is The Matrix (which is far more complicated still, in the system required to realize it); so to get even better than that (even all the way to a perfect Cartesian Demon) requires a vastly more complex hypothesis than even that (necessarily, as discussed in The God Impossible). Just to construct and describe its powers and motives and how and why it has them. Worse, you then also have to still propose a whole extra universe on top of the Cartesian Demon anyway, in which the Cartesian Demon can exist and which makes its powers realizable. Just skipping the vast added complexity of the demon and sticking with that universe you need in the explanation anyway is by definition far simpler.

So, Cartesian Demons are simply too improbable to credit on present undeniable evidence (particularly the undeniable present experience of all these logical facts). That’s epistemically improbable, of course. We may well be brains in vats. But we have no reason at all to believe that that’s in any way likely. Mediated perception of an external reality more or less accurately modeled by our brain is just a far simpler and thus epistemically more likely explanation of how these perception events are occurring as they are. And that conclusion requires no infinite regress, no circular argument.

Discover more from Richard Carrier Blogs

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading