A question is being asked a lot lately: how can the most prominent position held by scientists and philosophers be that consciousness doesn’t exist? Obviously consciousness exists. It’s literally the only thing you can know with absolute 100% certainty. “I think, therefore I am.” Cartesian knowledge. That you are experiencing certain things right now is literally undeniable. Your sense of “self,” what you are thinking and feeling, sights and sounds integrated into a unified sensory field, your ability to reason in a stream of connected thoughts and be aware that you are doing so. That you are experiencing these things when you are cannot be denied. What that means, of course, can be doubted. Does it mean there is a physical world, that you are the operational product of a complex wetware computer called a brain? Or is anything you are experiencing real at all, as opposed to just a fantasy or hallucination or lucid dream? Is solipsism true? Or are we just brains in a vat? Does our consciousness prove we have a disembodied soul? Or that anyone even could?

I’ve already covered the question of how we know the external world is real and all that jazz, and that our consciousness is communicating information to us and not just making everything up (see my discussion of Cartesian Demons for a start). And most people get that distinction, how consciousness can be a construct yet still be communicating information about reality apart from it. But the question seems to be now that experts are claiming that even the construct doesn’t exist, that “consciousness its very self” doesn’t exist. An example of a work going around leading people to think that this is what’s being said is Daniel Dennett’s “Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 (2016). Dennett himself never uses any language like “consciousness doesn’t exist.” That is usually formulated by people opposing his point, because they fail to get his point. But in common English saying “consciousness is an illusion” is saying “consciousness doesn’t exist.” And this failure to appreciate everyday semantics is an all-too-common error in academic philosophy today. I’m here to correct that mistake.

Philosophers Need to Start Taking Colloquial Semantics More Seriously

I’ve had issues with this entire trend in philosophy called Eliminativism, where all sorts of things are claimed not to exist that actually do—like “truth” or “propositions.” This is actually just shitty semantics; no one who actually advances such a view actually means these things don’t exist at all, but only that they are different things than is usually assumed. So they shouldn’t be using words and phrases like “eliminativism” (no, you have not “eliminated” truth and propositions; you’ve simply redefined what you think they are, which is not the same thing) or “doesn’t exist” (no, you mean, the thing as traditionally conceived doesn’t exist; but that something does very much exist, it’s just a different thing than commonly thought). I’ve already explained this point before with respect to “truth” and “propositions” (and even “beliefs”) as claimed “not to exist” by the otherwise-excellent philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland (see “Giving the Churchlands a Fairer Shake” in my Critical Review of Reppert). Tl;dr: they actually just argue these exist as different things than usually thought, not that they don’t exist “at all.” So, honestly, that’s what they should have frackin said.

I discuss an early example of this in Sense and Goodness without God (index), for common parlance regarding a “life force.” The traditional and common superstition that this is some force that hovers around living things like a magnetic field and that has powers conveying vitality is indeed false. But what the phrase “life force” was keying on (what people actually observe when saying it is present or absent) does exist: a certain emergent behavior of active metabolic systems defining life vs. nonlife or even death. We have simply explained that entirely now as a system of chemical and electrical interactions sustained by a material platform (usually consisting of genes and cells, which reduce to atoms, arranged in a certain way). There is no “force” or “field” corresponding. But the physical system can generate standard physical forces, and thus make decisions, move around; in a word, live. Vitality is real. It does exist. It just isn’t a seperate physical substance or fundamental force. Just as heat is real, yet isn’t a distinct substance as once we thought, but the emergent effect of a complex system of physical causes among things none of which by itself is “heat” or even meaningfully “hot.” That still doesn’t mean we can say heat “doesn’t exist.” We just have a better idea now of what it is and what causes it.

The Semantics of Illusionism

So when philosophers talk about consciousness not existing or being only an illusion, I think this is a semantic mistake. Which is a common error in academic philosophy these days, due I think to the total abandonment of Ordinary Language Philosophy as a trend without salvaging what it got right (just like the foolish abandonment of the entirety of Logical Positivism without, again, salvaging what it got right), one of many wrong moves the field has made of late. Though many of the propositions and insistences and conclusions of OLP were wrong (or at least wrongheaded), it had some key positions entirely correct. Among them: ordinary everyday language is fundamental to philosophical analysis and must always be attended to and not abandoned, not under any excuse. Yes, jargon and formalisms are useful. But if you cannot immediately tie them to how most people ordinarily speak and understand words, you have failed them, and thus failed one of the most essential goals of philosophy as an enterprise.

Accordingly, one should never write a whole, lengthy paper about how consciousness is an illusion and never qualify that by explaining that this does not mean to say consciousness doesn’t exist. Because an Ordinary Language Philosopher doing their job would recognize that in popular colloquial English “it’s an illusion” and “it doesn’t exist” in most contexts mean the same thing, and therefore to not qualify contextually what you mean is to forget how ordinary English works and therefore cause all manner of ubiquitous misunderstanding. That even professional philosophers are thereby confused by it only makes the point worse—as you can’t then retreat behind “fuck ordinary people; I only care about what the ivory tower thinks” either. Because, well, even the ivory tower is failing to get your point. And that’s on you, buddy. Attend to plain language. That will correct most of this. (Yes, many people, lay and expert, are also bad at language and fail to understand even clear sentences in English, but you can’t fix every problem in the world by speaking clearly.)

So here’s the antidote. Consciousness is certainly an illusion, in the same way colors and mirages are illusions. But illusions still exist. To confuse “that mirage is an illusion” with “that mirage doesn’t exist” is a semantic error that (inexplicably) even many expert philosophers are making here. A mirage exists. Indeed, it even physically exists outside the mind: it’s refracted light on a radiated heat differential, forming a pattern similar to reflections from water. It just isn’t water. The illusion is as to what it is, not that it exists. Colors are a good example: nothing in the world has a color. Nothing is red or green. Our brains made that up as a way to represent a much more complicated fact (patterns of photon-frequency reflections and refractions and the like) in a simple enough way to make practical use of. But that does not mean colors don’t exist. They are illusions, yes. We are being tricked into thinking things in the world have those colors, and it took us centuries of sophisticated science to discover that fact. Even Newton believed colors were things in the world, that light was “colored.” But it was later shown that light is just photons vibrating at certain frequencies; color is then manufactured in the brain as a fiction to represent that. But this still means colors are real; the brain really is inventing them, you really are experiencing them. That is in fact the whole point of colors: if they didn’t exist, we couldn’t make use of them in the way we do.

Consciousness is an illusion in the same sense: it is a model our brains build of what’s going on “in” our brain, and in so doing it might invent some things that serve roles as colors do, things that don’t exist apart from the model or the system building it, but that are useful for representing something else that does exist (neurons, information processing, and the like). For example, our sense of time is actually constructed out of 1/10th-to-1/20th-second moments, such that we are “tricked” by film reels into not seeing the walls on each cell of film and instead seeing continuous motion. Illusion—but still a real thing that’s happening. And indeed, here the illusion is obviously intentional. We are supposed to understand continuous motion is occurring (even though it isn’t). That’s the point of setting film frame rates at 1/24th-a-second. So, yes, that we are seeing continuous motion when we watch a movie or TV-show is an illusion. But the illusion itself remains real: it is actually happening, we are actually experiencing it, and that is the entire point of creating the illusion. To borrow Dennett’s analogy, that the magician just sawed a women in half is an illusion, yes; but there are still a saw and two boxes, one with a woman’s head popping out, and another with feet, peculiarly resembling hers. There is still something that exists here. It just isn’t what we are meant to believe is there.

I think the best way to “translate” what Dennett and the like are trying to say that doesn’t make a hash of the English language, is that anything “experienced” in our mind does indeed exist, but as a trick our brain pulls on us, and not some sort of Platonic second substance we have to account for with some weird ontology. Tricks still exist though. So to say it is a trick is not, in ordinary language, to say it doesn’t exist. That would be a semantic mistake. And anyone making that mistake easy to make, or outright making it, is failing at philosophy. To be fair, Dennett is not the worst offender here, he just buries this information in hundreds of words that beat around without ever clearly getting to this crucial point that illusions still exist, they are still real—as illusions. And indeed, that is what he is trying to explain: how “qualia” (the philosopher’s catch-all word for all the particular possibles of experience, from colors to sounds to smells to feelings and thoughts and the whole show) come to exist. They exist as illusions. Like the two boxes, one with a smiling assistant peaking out, the other with some mannequin feet wearing her same shoes, and a saw in between. To think anything more has happened is like thinking this woman was just actually cut in half—or that some magical quantum portal must connect the two boxes. Instead, those are dumb theories. Likewise most attempts at explaining consciousness.

One way to frame this in a way that’s more helpful than you might be encountering is to think of qualia in the context of the p-zombie problem. A “p-zombie” is a “philosophical zombie,” a conceptual entity wherein we have an exact copy of you (exact same brain, down to every exact same synapse and neural behavior, same chemical interactions, same electrical signals) that differs from you in only one respect: they don’t experience qualia. So, for example, they can discriminate, even name and identify, colors exactly as you do, but they don’t “experience” colors. They have no idea what “red” looks like. They experience nothing. They just exhibit the requisite knowledge and behavior. The attempt to insist qualia are independently real (and not a trick or illusion) has indeed been to posit a p-zombie. But this actually fails to work as they want; in fact, their own thought experiment verifies everything Dennett is saying.

I’ve already explained this in detail before in my section on zombies in On Hosing Thought Experiments (which gives many more examples of academic philosophers making similar semantic mistakes as I am fixing here, illustrating the problem is endemic and not just particular to this topic; indeed, note how the entire Free Will debate can be characterized as deriving without remainder from a singular semantic mistake of similar kind: see Why Syllogisms Usually Suck: Free Will Edition and Free Will in the Real World … and Why It Matters). Tl;dr: to make it work as described, the p-zombie would have to either lie when asked if it experiences qualia (which would be a difference of behavior, with observably different brain functions, ruling it out as a p-zombie) or actually sincerely believe it is seeing qualia when it is not (since reporting it does not, would be a difference of behavior again, with observably different brain functions, again ruling it out as a p-zombie). But what’s the difference between merely believing you are experiencing qualia, and actually experiencing qualia? Dennett is saying there is no difference, so there is nothing more left to explain.

This is not actually saying qualia (the experiences themselves) don’t exist; it is rather saying that some other thing—let’s call it “pqualia,” the David-Chalmers-style “second substance” thingamawhatsit everyone thinks is some extra thing we have yet to explain—doesn’t exist. There are no pqualia. There are only qualia. Just as there is no phlogiston and no fundamental life force (and no Libertarian Freewill and no Platonic Forms and so on and on). And those saying this are right. All evidence does point to this. Pqualia is an epicycle, angels pushing the planets. “We have no need of that hypothesis.” Qualia as useful illusion is the simplest explanation that fits all the facts, and thus indeed, as Dennett says, should therefore be the default; and the burden then put on pqualia advocates to prove their harebrained thing even exists. But one should not confuse that for saying qualia don’t exist. Because illusions still exist; and something still is creating them.

The Ontology of Consciousness

The objection is usually made that this can’t be true. Consciousness can’t be an illusion, because all these other illusions (colors etc.) are being presented to someone; illusions still require an observer. That “someone” can’t themselves be an illusion. But the fact that that isn’t true is precisely Dennett’s point. There is no literal “someone” to whom things are being “presented.” There is no little homunculus inside you watching your thoughts like a theater. That you feel like there is is the illusion. But that feeling, the experiencing of things in that way, remains real. It’s actually happening. Consciousness thus exists. It just isn’t the thing you thought it was. Like all those other things we had mistaken ideas about (from heat to life force to free will to abstract objects and beliefs and propositional knowledge and beyond).

Consciousness is a construct, a computational model—and as such, it is an illusion of something else. For example, that you are a single unified person observing all things from a single Cartesian point. That’s fake. Useful. But fake. “You” are actually spread out over dozens of disparate information processing systems and data storage registers across your brain that don’t operate in perfect simultaneity much less exist at a single point or even have a common purpose. And qualia (the entire content of consciousness, from colors to feelings to thoughts) don’t exist outside your mere belief that they do. They are not located at any point in spacetime; they have no mass or energy; they are not made of anything. They simply are what it is to process information a certain way. It “feels” like it feels, and that’s it. There is no more substance to it. Hence this is all an illusion insofar as this computation tricks us into thinking there is more to it than that (see The Bogus Idea of the Bogus Mysteries of Consciousness). For example, that colors exist outside our mind; they don’t. Or that emotions are something more than the product of independent information processing neural circuits separated from much of the rest of what constitutes us; they aren’t. And so on. Even the sense that our mind could exist without the brain, that it could leave the body and continue working. Nope. That’s an illusion. Our brain is tricking itself into thinking that’s the case, by creating the illusion of this singular disembodied person watching it all. We experience consciousness this way because our brain’s computations make us think we do. And for no other reason.

So when someone says “but illusions require an observer,” this is to conflate “observer” with “consciousness of observing.” My computer’s motion sensing system is an observer of events in my room; it is not conscious. Even worms and robots count as “observers.” We are not here trying to explain observers. We are here trying to explain consciousness of being an observer, the “what it is like” aspect of it; hence, qualia (which includes emotions and thoughts, everything “experiency,” not just sensory perceptions). There is no “person” inside my computer observing me move cross the room; yet it is observing me cross the room. There is no “person” inside a fly observing a light across the way; yet it is observing a light across the way. The peculiar thing is not “there are observers.” The peculiar thing is “why it feels the way it does to be an observer.” In humans, a distinct part of that is a self-model: our brains build a model of a unified system of goals and perspectives, which represents the brain as a whole being an observer. That is made-up. Useful. But made-up. We feel like this is the case, because our brains compute that it is the case.

For example, in our brains we have separate systems processing sound and vision; but our brains then unify them into a single integrated model. That integration is a construct; it does not exist apart from the information processing that produces it. More importantly (as science has conclusively proved by now) it does not exist in some separate place all its own—there is no point in the brain where we can say “the unification occurs there.” The unification is occurring across the whole brain. Likewise, all your thoughts, emotions, motivations: your brain invents a coherent model of all those disparate things and integrates it into the sensory field produced, making you feel like there is a single point-observer watching it all. That’s fake. Useful. But fake. No such single point-observer exists in the brain. There is no place you can point to. It’s an output spanning multiple brain systems, a perspective that the brain as a whole has stitched together, manufactured, as a useful fiction (see The Mind Is a Process Not an Object: On Not Understanding Mind-Brain Physicalism).

Indeed, we know it takes about half a second to process this fiction; hence, fact is, we already made a decision and processed the why of it half a second before we become aware that we made that decision and why. “We” as in the whole of us (our memories, reasoning, character, personality, skills, attitudes, values, etc.) still made that decision, and usually indeed for the very reasoning we then become conscious of. But our awareness of that, as a unified and coherent model of what just happened, is a computed product of the brain, one that as such took it time to complete and render. “But you’re saying it didn’t render it ‘to’ anyone.” No. Who it rendered “to” is you, the brain as a whole. The feeling of what this is like, of sitting at the center watching it all, like someone in the audience separate from it, is all a construct, a useful fiction. The experience is the illusion. Not what it is an experience of. That’s real. No one actually means to say consciousness is just our brain making everything up all willy nilly. There is a real you with real thoughts and feelings and real perceptions. It’s just how it is presented, what it feels like, that is fictional. And the illusion, too, is also real. No one is actually intending to say the illusion doesn’t exist either. You really are feeling like that. It’s just that we don’t require anything more to explain that than that you believe you are. And we don’t require anything more to exlain that, than that your brain has computed you are. That’s Dennett’s point. There is no “extra something” required. That computed “belief” is all there is.

Conclusion

Again to be clear (as Dennett sometimes is not), to call all this a fiction is not to say that its content (what it represents) is false or that its referents don’t exist. There is a brain; it shares a volume in your head; it occupies and operates one and only one body; and it’s thinking and evaluating, and moving around in a world arranged more or less like you think it is. So to simulate this with a fiction of a unified perspective, a singular observer “to whom” everything seems presented, is not wholly inaccurate. But it does mislead in respect to its core attribute, which is why so many philosophers (and so many more laypeople) still have confused themselves into thinking qualia must be some magical second substance and consciousness some real central entity that merely sits aside and observes what the brain presents it, and then gives it instructions. Thus the illusion of consciousness has misled us into thinking there must be something “more” to make this possible, that there must be some extra separate entity “to whom” this is all presented. But that’s precisely the illusion being created. It isn’t what’s actually happening.

This is still a useful illusion, though, because every aspect of it corresponds to something true about you and the world. Just like colors: they are fictions, but useful because our brain attempts to correlate them with real information about the external world. They are simply a convenient way to represent and analyze information. The information is still real. What it corresponds to is still real. And what it feels like to compute it is still real. The room you are in is layed out as you think, the objects in it really are where you think, and so on. The colors, the representation of objects as solid, these are fictions your brain uses to model all these things. And this can mislead you (as it did almost all humanity until relatively recently) into thinking objects in the world really look like that—really have colors (rather than only reflecting or refracting electromagnetic field quanta), really are solid (rather than almost entirely empty space), and so on. But even once we know that, it’s still all usable data about real things. Thanks to the repulsion of the electromagnetic force, we really can’t walk through objects we perceive as solid; visible-light photons really aren’t passing through them; and so on. So calling colors an illusion, fictions invented by our brain, is not sayng they don’t exist, nor even that they don’t correspond to any real thing.

Hence, likewise, the “Cartesian Theater” illusion does represent some key information correctly, and only fabricates the “theater” perspective so as to compute all that information conveniently. You are a single brain in a single body and thus all parts of you do share some common interests and goals, and organizing those into a singular focusable purpose is useful in precisely all the ways we observe it to be. Obviously. Just look at everything we can and have accomplished with this ability, as persons and a people. This illusion continues to create information as well, as the more you “think about yourself and your life” a certain way, the more this becomes narrative memory stored in the brain and thus becomes even more a part of you. You are thus not a random jumble of reactions, feelings, perceptions, and desires. You, as a definable person, an individual, a “self,” do indeed exist; indeed your brain has been building this personal identity since birth. You exist as all the stored information about “you” in your brain, and its physical neural interconnections; and you get to experience informational reports about you (what “you,” as in your brain, are thinking, seeing, feeling, deciding), as your brain computes them; and those computed outputs do indeed become inputs in future reasoning and thinking and causal development of you as a person. Thus all of this exists. It just doesn’t exist as what it superficially seems or feels like, just as colors do not. But just as colors are useful and represent real things apart from them, so is your conscious self-model, your experience of what it is like to be you.

Discover more from Richard Carrier Blogs

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading